No Words Wasted Sale
 
 

Special Offers see all

Enter to WIN a $100 Credit

Subscribe to PowellsBooks.news
for a chance to win.
Privacy Policy

Visit our stores


    Recently Viewed clear list


    Original Essays | January 14, 2015

    Marie Mutsuki Mockett: IMG On Trimming Roses



    Gardens do not wait. Weeds grow and flowers wilt. In the days and weeks following my father's death, my parents' garden continued to flourish and... Continue »
    1. $18.87 Sale Hardcover add to wish list

    spacer
Qualifying orders ship free.
$7.98
List price: $15.00
Sale Trade Paper
Ships in 1 to 3 days
Add to Wishlist
Qty Store Section
4 Beaverton History- Sale Books
1 Burnside Politics- General

Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do?

by

Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do? Cover

ISBN13: 9780374532505
ISBN10: 0374532508
Condition:
All Product Details

 

 

Excerpt

1. DOING THE RIGHT THING

In the summer of 2004, Hurricane Charley roared out of the Gulf of Mexico and swept across Florida to the Atlantic Ocean. The storm claimed twenty-two lives and caused $11 billion in damage.1 It also left in its wake a debate about price gouging.

At a gas station in Orlando, they were selling two-dollar bags of ice for ten dollars. Lacking power for refrigerators or air-conditioning in the middle of August, many people had little choice but to pay up. Downed trees heightened demand for chain saws and roof repairs. Contractors offered to clear two trees off a homeowners roof—for $23,000. Stores that normally sold small household generators for $250 were now asking $2,000. A seventy-seven-year-old woman fleeing the hurricane with her elderly husband and handicapped daughter was charged $160 per night for a motel room that normally goes for $40.2

Many Floridians were angered by the inflated prices. “After Storm Come the Vultures,” read a headline in USA Today. One resident, told it would cost $10,500 to remove a fallen tree from his roof, said it was wrong for people to “try to capitalize on other peoples hardship and misery.” Charlie Crist, the states attorney general, agreed: “It is astounding to me, the level of greed that someone must have in their soul to be willing to take advantage of someone suffering in the wake of a hurricane.”3

Florida has a law against price gouging, and in the aftermath of the hurricane, the attorney generals office received more than two thousand complaints. Some led to successful lawsuits. A Days Inn in West Palm Beach had to pay $70,000 in penalties and restitution for overcharging customers.4

But even as Crist set about enforcing the price-gouging law, some economists argued that the law—and the public outrage—were misconceived. In medieval times, philosophers and theologians believed that the exchange of goods should be governed by a “just price,” determined by tradition or the intrinsic value of things. But in market societies, the economists observed, prices are set by supply and demand. There is no such thing as a “just price.”

Thomas Sowell, a free-market economist, called price gouging an “emotionally powerful but economically meaningless expression that most economists pay no attention to, because it seems too confused to bother with.” Writing in the Tampa Tribune, Sowell sought to explain “how ‘price gouging helps Floridians.” Charges of price gouging arise “when prices are significantly higher than what people have been used to,” Sowell wrote. But “the price levels that you happen to be used to” are not morally sacrosanct. They are no more “special or ‘fair than other prices” that market conditions—including those prompted by a hurricane—may bring about.5

Higher prices for ice, bottled water, roof repairs, generators, and motel rooms have the advantage, Sowell argued, of limiting the use of such things by consumers and increasing incentives for suppliers in far-off places to provide the goods and ser vices most needed in the hurricanes aftermath. If ice fetches ten dollars a bag when Floridians are facing power outages in the August heat, ice manufacturers will find it worth their while to produce and ship more of it. There is nothing unjust about these prices, Sowell explained; they simply reflect the value that buyers and sellers choose to place on the things they exchange.6

Jeff Jacoby, a pro-market commentator writing in the Boston Globe, argued against price-gouging laws on similar grounds: “It isnt gouging to charge what the market will bear. It isnt greedy or brazen. Its how goods and ser vices get allocated in a free society.” Jacoby acknowledged that the “price spikes are infuriating, especially to someone whose life has just been thrown into turmoil by a deadly storm.” But public anger is no justification for interfering with the free market. By providing incentives for suppliers to produce more of the needed goods, the seemingly exorbitant prices “do far more good than harm.” His conclusion: “Demonizing vendors wont speed Floridas recovery. Letting them go about their business will.”7

Attorney General Crist (a Republican who would later be elected governor of Florida) published an op-ed piece in the Tampa paper defending the law against price gouging: “In times of emergency, government cannot remain on the sidelines while people are charged unconscionable prices as they flee for their lives or seek the basic commodities for their families after a hurricane.”8 Crist rejected the notion that these “unconscionable” prices reflected a truly free exchange:

This is not the normal free market situation where willing buyers freely elect to enter into the marketplace and meet willing sellers, where a price is agreed upon based on supply and demand. In an emergency, buyers under duress have no freedom. Their purchases of necessities like safe lodging are forced.9

The debate about price gouging that arose in the aftermath of Hurricane Charley raises hard questions of morality and law: Is it wrong for sellers of goods and ser vices to take advantage of a natural disaster by charging whatever the market will bear? If so, what, if anything, should the law do about it? Should the state prohibit price gouging, even if doing so interferes with the freedom of buyers and sellers to make whatever deals they choose?

Welfare, Freedom, and Virtue

These questions are not only about how individuals should treat one another. They are also about what the law should be, and about how society should be organized. They are questions about justice. To answer them, we have to explore the meaning of justice. In fact, weve already begun to do so. If you look closely at the price-gouging debate, youll notice that the arguments for and against price-gouging laws revolve around three ideas: maximizing welfare, respecting freedom, and promoting virtue. Each of these ideas points to a different way of thinking about justice.

The standard case for unfettered markets rests on two claims—one about welfare, the other about freedom. First, markets promote the welfare of society as a whole by providing incentives for people to work hard supplying the goods that other people want. (In common parlance, we often equate welfare with economic prosperity, though welfare is a broader concept that can include noneconomic aspects of social well-being.) Second, markets respect individual freedom; rather than impose a certain value on goods and ser vices, markets let people choose for themselves what value to place on the things they exchange.

Not surprisingly, the opponents of price-gouging laws invoke these two familiar arguments for free markets. How do defenders of price gouging laws respond? First, they argue that the welfare of society as whole is not really served by the exorbitant prices charged in hard times. Even if high prices call forth a greater supply of goods, this benefit has to be weighed against the burden such prices impose on those least able to afford them. For the affluent, paying inflated prices for a gallon of gas or a motel room in a storm may be an annoyance; but for those of modest means, such prices pose a genuine hardship, one that might lead them to stay in harms way rather than flee to safety. Proponents of price-gouging laws argue that any estimate of the general welfare must include the pain and suffering of those who may be priced out of basic necessities during an emergency.

Second, defenders of price-gouging laws maintain that, under certain conditions, the free market is not truly free. As Crist points out, “buyers under duress have no freedom. Their purchases of necessities like safe lodging are forced.” If youre fleeing a hurricane with your family, the exorbitant price you pay for gas or shelter is not really a voluntary exchange. Its something closer to extortion. So to decide whether price-gouging laws are justified, we need to assess these competing accounts of welfare and of freedom.

But we also need to consider one further argument. Much public support for price-gouging laws comes from something more visceral than welfare or freedom. People are outraged at “vultures” who prey on the desperation of others and want them punished—not rewarded with windfall profits. Such sentiments are often dismissed as atavistic emotions that should not interfere with public policy or law. As Jacoby writes, “demonizing vendors wont speed Floridas recovery.”10

But the outrage at price-gougers is more than mindless anger. It gestures at a moral argument worth taking seriously. Outrage is the special kind of anger you feel when you believe that people are getting things they dont deserve. Outrage of this kind is anger at injustice.

Crist touched on the moral source of the outrage when he described the “greed that someone must have in their soul to be willing to take advantage of someone suffering in the wake of a hurricane.” He did not explicitly connect this observation to price-gouging laws. But implicit in his comment is something like the following argument, which might be called the virtue argument:

Greed is a vice, a bad way of being, especially when it makes people oblivious to the suffering of others. More than a personal vice, it is at odds with civic virtue. In times of trouble, a good society pulls together. Rather than press for maximum advantage, people look out for one another. A society in which people exploit their neighbors for financial gain in times of crisis is not a good society. Excessive greed is therefore a vice that a good society should discourage if it can. Pricegouging laws cannot banish greed, but they can at least restrain its most brazen expression, and signal societys disapproval of it. By punishing greedy behavior rather than rewarding it, society affirms the civic virtue of shared sacrifice for the common good.

To acknowledge the moral force of the virtue argument is not to insist that it must always prevail over competing considerations. You might conclude, in some instances, that a hurricane-stricken community should make a devils bargain—allow price gouging in hopes of attracting an army of roofers and contractors from far and wide, even at the moral cost of sanctioning greed. Repair the roofs now and the social fabric later. Whats important to notice, however, is that the debate about price-gouging laws is not simply about welfare and freedom. It is also about virtue—about cultivating the attitudes and dispositions, the qualities of character, on which a good society depends.

Some people, including many who support price-gouging laws, find the virtue argument discomfiting. The reason: It seems more judgmental than arguments that appeal to welfare and freedom. To ask whether a policy will speed economic recovery or spur economic growth does not involve judging peoples preferences. It assumes that everyone prefers more income rather than less, and it doesnt pass judgment on how they spend their money. Similarly, to ask whether, under conditions of duress, people are actually free to choose doesnt require evaluating their choices. The question is whether, or to what extent, people are free rather than coerced.

The virtue argument, by contrast, rests on a judgment that greed is a vice that the state should discourage. But who is to judge what is virtue and what is vice? Dont citizens of pluralist societies disagree about such things? And isnt it dangerous to impose judgments about virtue through law? In the face of these worries, many people hold that government should be neutral on matters of virtue and vice; it should not try to cultivate good attitudes or discourage bad ones.

So when we probe our reactions to price gouging, we find ourselves pulled in two directions: We are outraged when people get things they dont deserve; greed that preys on human misery, we think, should be punished, not rewarded. And yet we worry when judgments about virtue find their way into law.

This dilemma points to one of the great questions of political philosophy: Does a just society seek to promote the virtue of its citizens? Or should law be neutral toward competing conceptions of virtue, so that citizens can be free to choose for themselves the best way to live?

According to the textbook account, this question divides ancient and modern political thought. In one important respect, the textbook is right. Aristotle teaches that justice means giving people what they deserve. And in order to determine who deserves what, we have to determine what virtues are worthy of honor and reward. Aristotle maintains that we cant figure out what a just constitution is without first reflecting on the most desirable way of life. For him, law cant be neutral on questions of the good life.

By contrast, modern political philosophers—from Immanuel Kant in the eighteenth century to John Rawls in the twentieth century—argue that the principles of justice that define our rights should not rest on any particular conception of virtue, or of the best way to live. Instead, a just society respects each persons freedom to choose his or her own conception of the good life.

So you might say that ancient theories of justice start with virtue, while modern theories start with freedom. And in the chapters to come, we explore the strengths and weaknesses of each. But its worth noticing at the outset that this contrast can mislead.

For if we turn our gaze to the arguments about justice that animate contemporary politics—not among philosophers but among ordinary men and women—we find a more complicated picture. Its true that most of our arguments are about promoting prosperity and respecting individual freedom, at least on the surface. But underlying these arguments, and sometimes contending with them, we can often glimpse another set of convictions—about what virtues are worthy of honor and reward, and what way of life a good society should promote. Devoted though we are to prosperity and freedom, we cant quite shake off the judgmental strand of justice. The conviction that justice involves virtue as well as choice runs deep. Thinking about justice seems inescapably to engage us in thinking about the best way to live.

What Wounds Deserve the Purple Heart?

On some issues, questions of virtue and honor are too obvious to deny. Consider the recent debate over who should qualify for the Purple Heart. Since 1932, the U.S. military has awarded the medal to soldiers wounded or killed in battle by enemy action. In addition to the honor, the medal entitles recipients to special privileges in veterans hospitals.

Since the beginning of the current wars in Iraq and Afghanistan, growing numbers of veterans have been diagnosed with post-traumatic stress disorder and treated for the condition. Symptoms include recurring nightmares, severe depression, and suicide. At least three hundred thousand veterans reportedly suffer from traumatic stress or major depression. Advocates for these veterans have proposed that they, too, should qualify for the Purple Heart. Since psychological injuries can be at least as debilitating as physical ones, they argue, soldiers who suffer these wounds should receive the medal.11

After a Pentagon advisory group studied the question, the Pentagon announced, in 2009, that the Purple Heart would be reserved for soldiers with physical injuries. Veterans suffering from mental disorders and psychological trauma would not be eligible, even though they qualify for government-supported medical treatment and disability payments. The Pentagon offered two reasons for its decision: traumatic stress disorders are not intentionally caused by enemy action, and they are difficult to diagnose objectively.12

Did the Pentagon make the right decision? Taken by themselves, its reasons are unconvincing. In the Iraq War, one of the most common injuries recognized with the Purple Heart has been a punctured eardrum, caused by explosions at close range.13 But unlike bullets and bombs, such explosions are not a deliberate enemy tactic intended to injure or kill; they are (like traumatic stress) a damaging side effect of battlefield action. And while traumatic disorders may be more difficult to diagnose than a broken limb, the injury they inflict can be more severe and long-lasting.

As the wider debate about the Purple Heart revealed, the real issue is about the meaning of the medal and the virtues it honors. What, then, are the relevant virtues? Unlike other military medals, the Purple Heart honors sacrifice, not bravery. It requires no heroic act, only an injury inflicted by the enemy. The question is what kind of injury should count.

A veterans group called the Military Order of the Purple Heart opposed awarding the medal for psychological injuries, claiming that doing so would “debase” the honor. A spokesman for the group stated that “shedding blood” should be an essential qualification.14 He didnt explain why bloodless injuries shouldnt count. But Tyler E. Boudreau, a former Marine captain who favors including psychological injuries, offers a compelling analysis of the dispute. He attributes the opposition to a deep-seated attitude in the military that views post-traumatic stress as a kind of weakness. “The same culture that demands tough-mindedness also encourages skepticism toward the suggestion that the violence of war can hurt the healthiest of minds … Sadly, as long as our military culture bears at least a quiet contempt for the psychological wounds of war, it is unlikely those veterans will ever see a Purple Heart.”15

So the debate over the Purple Heart is more than a medical or clinical dispute about how to determine the veracity of injury. At the heart of the disagreement are rival conceptions of moral character and military valor. Those who insist that only bleeding wounds should count believe that post-traumatic stress reflects a weakness of character unworthy of honor. Those who believe that psychological wounds should qualify argue that veterans suffering long-term trauma and severe depression have sacrificed for their country as surely, and as honorably, as those whove lost a limb.

The dispute over the Purple Heart illustrates the moral logic of Aristotles theory of justice. We cant determine who deserves a military medal without asking what virtues the medal properly honors. And to answer that question, we have to assess competing conceptions of character and sacrifice.

It might be argued that military medals are a special case, a throwback to an ancient ethic of honor and virtue. These days, most of our arguments about justice are about how to distribute the fruits of prosperity, or the burdens of hard times, and how to define the basic rights of citizens. In these domains, considerations of welfare and freedom predominate. But arguments about the rights and wrongs of economic arrangements often lead us back to Aristotles question of what people morally deserve, and why.

Bailout Outrage

The public furor over the financial crisis of 2008-09 is a case in point. For years, stock prices and real estate values had climbed. The reckoning came when the housing bubble burst. Wall Street banks and financial institutions had made billions of dollars on complex investments backed by mortgages whose value now plunged. Once proud Wall Street firms teetered on the edge of collapse. The stock market tanked, devastating not only big investors but also ordinary Americans, whose retirement accounts lost much of their value. The total wealth of American families fell by $11 trillion in 2008, an amount equal to the combined annual output of Germany, Japan, and the UK.16

In October 2008, President George W. Bush asked Congress for $700 billion to bail out the nations big banks and financial firms. It didnt seem fair that Wall Street had enjoyed huge profits during the good times and was now asking taxpayers to foot the bill when things had gone bad. But there seemed no alternative. The banks and financial firms had grown so vast and so entwined with every aspect of the economy that their collapse might bring down the entire financial system. They were “too big to fail.”

Excerpted from Justice: Whats the right thing to do? by Michael J. Sandel.

Copyright © 2009 by Michael J. Sandel.

Published in 2009 by Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

All rights reserved. This work is protected under copyright laws and reproduction is strictly prohibited. Permission to reproduce the material in any manner or medium must be secured from the Publisher.

What Our Readers Are Saying

Add a comment for a chance to win!
Average customer rating based on 1 comment:

Rick Vigorous, July 29, 2014 (view all comments by Rick Vigorous)
This short book is based on the famous course of the same name that Sandel has taught for many years at Harvard. The main strength of the book--and no doubt of his lectures as well--is the way in which he begins with examples of moral dilemmas, and then from there attempts to extract general principles from the arguments that these examples lead to. Apparently this process is what is meant by the term “philosophical dialectic.” Sandel’s idea of political philosophy is that it is not an armchair pursuit, but fundamentally requires engagement between two or more parties, and ideally all the rest of society as well. Sandel's examples are chosen with sufficient care that they clearly illustrate the point that needs illustrating, sufficiently realistic to engage the reader’s interest, and sufficiently controversial that reasonable people might disagree about it and be able to have a productive argument. I think the last of these is especially crucial.

A few of the many illustrative examples:
* Is it permissible for starving sailors to cannibalize the cabin boy while stranded at sea? Utilitarian reasoning says yes, but Kant would claim that human dignity is paramount and cannot be accounted for by utilitarian calculations.
* Is torture ever justified?
* Is it alright for Romans to feed Christians to the lions if the public wants it?
* Is it just for a country to hire soldiers rather than drafting them?
* Is it fair to rent out one’s womb as a surrogate mother, or to sell one’s organs, particularly if the seller is poor and desperate for money? What about selling votes, or hiring substitutes for juries?
* Is affirmative action fair?

The overall scheme of the book is to compare three rival theories of justice. The first, utilitarianism, traces back to Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill. The basic idea is that one ought to “maximize utility” by doing whatever leads to the greatest good for the greatest number of people. There are two main challenges to this philosophy: (i) it does not respect individual rights and freedom (see the examples above about the cabin boy and feeding Christians to the lions), and (ii) perhaps not everything can be thought of in the same units of “moral currency” (e.g. a foreclosed home vs. a human life). John Stuart Mill’s work was largely an attempt to reconcile Bentham’s ideas with liberty and individual freedom. Insofar as he succeeded, he was really denouncing core utilitarian ideas.

The second main theory of justice is the modern liberal political philosophy, most strongly expressed in the writings of Kant and John Rawls. The goal of this school of thought has always been to develop a framework for law and civic life that is neutral with respect to differing ideas that people might have on what exactly constitutes the “good life.” Such an approach is clearly appealing in a pluralistic society encompassing people of multiple religious and cultural beliefs. In the end, however, Sandel becomes quite critical of the idea that such a program is possible or even desirable.

I found the chapter on Kant to be the most challenging one in the book. Kant’s basic ideas, which were largely formulated as a response to Bentham’s utilitarianism, revolve around fundamental principles of human dignity and freedom. He claimed that utilitarian philosophy is flawed because it allows people to be used as means to achieve other people’s happiness, whereas they ought to be viewed instead as ends in themselves. According to Kant, an act that gives us pleasure is not free, since we are merely acting as slaves to our desires. The crux of Kant’s moral philosophy is the categorical imperative. By “categorical” he means “unconditional,” i.e. independent of the particular consequences of a given action. For example, a shopkeeper who treats his customers well only because he wants their continued business is acting according to a hypothetical (concerned with the end result of continued business) rather than categorical (doing the right thing simply because it’s the right thing to do) imperative. In Kant’s famous formulation: “Act only on that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.”

As for Rawls, the main principles at play are the "veil of ignorance" and the difference principle. The first of these says that we should live according to a hypothetical social contract to which rational agents would agree without knowing anything about the sort of life they would happen to be born into. The agents would be unlikely to privilege the rich, for example, since they wouldn’t know whether they would be born rich or not. According to the difference principle, the rewards that are reaped by the most talented individuals must be applied to making the disadvantaged (e.g. the bottom quintile) better off. According to Rawls, distributive justice is not a matter of moral dessert, but of providing for those who are least well off.

The third main theory of justice comes from Aristotle. His conception of justice, as opposed to the utilitarian and liberal ideas discussed above, is fundamentally teleological, and so lacks the feeling of universality that’s present in the more modern theories. Suppose that we have a box of flutes. Whom should we give them to? The teleological answer to this question is that the flutes should go to the best flutists, since being played well is what the flutes are for. In a similar spirit, we might ask what people living together in a society are for, and Aristotle’s answer is--just as a flute’s purpose is to be played--that a society’s purpose is to cultivate virtue. This cultivation involves intellectual debate and being an engaged citizen and things like that. Of course, different people might have different ideas about what the best virtues to cultivate are, and herein lies the core difficulty of having a pluralistic society. Working through these differences is done through civic engagement and spirited discourse, but beyond this broad prescription neither Aristotle nor Sandel provides any easy answers.

Sandel eventually makes it clear that his own views of justice align most closely with Aristotle’s. I hadn’t expected things to end up this way, thinking that the more modern liberal theories must be more sophisticated, scientific, and correct. In effect, he’s saying that justice cannot be viewed as neatly and scientifically as one might hope, and that it’s necessarily tied up with competing ideas of what constitutes virtue and the good life. This is in the same spirit as the idea presented in Sandel’s newer book, What Money Can’t Buy, as well as in the talks and interviews I’ve seen him give. According to Sandel, markets are not as value-neutral and scientific as the economists would have us believe, and properly coming to terms with their role in our society necessarily means addressing difficult questions about value and virtue.

It’s a little disappointing that the author goes to all this trouble to convince the reader that moral behavior in the end depends on the particular details of what a society defines as virtue and what it chooses to value, and then hardly anything is said about what we should think of as virtuous or what we should value. There’s a sense in which it seems like the can has just been kicked down the road a bit. I would have liked very much to have read about a scientific method for determining in general terms what is the right thing to do. This is what Kant and Rawls tried to accomplish, but Sandel makes a compelling case that they were missing something. At least knowing that there may be no such general framework is quite valuable, even if it leaves the reader slightly unsatisfied. Perhaps there’s no shortcut to the sort of wisdom that I’d hoped to get from this book, and we can only hope that, like Tolstoy’s Pierre, we might one day find ourselves knowing what is the right thing to do after living life a bit more.
Was this comment helpful? | Yes | No
(1 of 2 readers found this comment helpful)

Product Details

ISBN:
9780374532505
Author:
Sandel, Michael J
Publisher:
Farrar Straus Giroux
Author:
Sandel, Michael J.
Subject:
Political
Subject:
History & Theory - General
Subject:
General Philosophy
Subject:
Values
Subject:
Ethics
Subject:
Philosophy : General
Subject:
Ethics & Moral Philosophy
Edition Description:
Trade Paperback
Publication Date:
20100831
Binding:
TRADE PAPER
Grade Level:
General/trade
Language:
English
Illustrations:
Includes Notes and an Index
Pages:
320
Dimensions:
8.25 x 5.56 x 0.85 in

Other books you might like

  1. The Sunflower: On the Possibilities... Used Trade Paper $9.00
  2. Logicomix: An Epic Search for Truth
    Used Trade Paper $16.50
  3. The Price of Altruism: George Price... Used Trade Paper $12.95
  4. No Future Without Forgiveness
    Used Trade Paper $9.95
  5. Lectures & Conversations on... Used Trade Paper $10.95
  6. How the Mind Works Used Trade Paper $5.50

Related Subjects


History and Social Science » Politics » General
History and Social Science » Sale Books
Humanities » Philosophy » Ethics
Humanities » Philosophy » General

Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do? Used Trade Paper
0 stars - 0 reviews
$7.98 In Stock
Product details 320 pages Farrar Straus Giroux - English 9780374532505 Reviews:
"Synopsis" by , Affirmative action, same-sex marriage, the moral limits of markets--Sandel relates the big questions of political philosophy to the most vexing issues of the day and shows how a surer grasp of philosophy can help us make sense of politics, morality, and our own convictions.
"Synopsis" by ,

“For Michael Sandel, justice is not a spectator sport,” The Nations reviewer of Justice remarked. In his acclaimed book—based on his legendary Harvard course—Sandel offers a rare education in thinking through the complicated issues and controversies we face in public life today. It has emerged as a most lucid and engaging guide for those who yearn for a more robust and thoughtful public discourse. “In terms we can all understand,” wrote Jonathan Rauch in The New York Times, Justice “confronts us with the concepts that lurk . . . beneath our conflicts.”

Affirmative action, same-sex marriage, physician-assisted suicide, abortion, national service, the moral limits of markets—Sandel relates the big questions of political philosophy to the most vexing issues of the day, and shows how a surer grasp of philosophy can help us make sense of politics, morality, and our own convictions as well.

Justice is lively, thought-provoking, and wise—an essential new addition to the small shelf of books that speak convincingly to the hard questions of our civic life.

"Synopsis" by ,

What are our obligations to others as people in a free society? Should government tax the rich to help the poor? Is the free market fair? Is it sometimes wrong to tell the truth? Is killing sometimes morally required? Is it possible, or desirable, to legislate morality? Do individual rights and the common good conflict?

Michael J. Sandels “Justice” course is one of the most popular and influential at Harvard. Up to a thousand students pack the campus theater to hear Sandel relate the big questions of political philosophy to the most vexing issues of the day, and this fall, public television will air a series based on the course. Justice offers readers the same exhilarating journey that captivates Harvard students. This book is a searching, lyrical exploration of the meaning of justice, one that invites readers of all political persuasions to consider familiar controversies in fresh and illuminating ways. Affirmative action, same-sex marriage, physician-assisted suicide, abortion, national service, patriotism and dissent, the moral limits of marketsSandel dramatizes the challenge of thinking through these con?icts, and shows how a surer grasp of philosophy can help us make sense of politics, morality, and our own convictions as well. Justice is lively, thought-provoking, and wisean essential new addition to the small shelf of books that speak convincingly to the hard questions of our civic life.

spacer
spacer
  • back to top

FOLLOW US ON...

     
Powell's City of Books is an independent bookstore in Portland, Oregon, that fills a whole city block with more than a million new, used, and out of print books. Shop those shelves — plus literally millions more books, DVDs, and gifts — here at Powells.com.